Volume 82, Issue 5 p. 1634-1647

Characterizing Children’s Expectations About Expertise and Incompetence: Halo or Pitchfork Effects?

Melissa A. Koenig

Melissa A. Koenig

University of Minnesota

Search for more papers by this author
Vikram K. Jaswal

Vikram K. Jaswal

University of Virginia

Search for more papers by this author
concerning this article should be addressed to Melissa A. Koenig, Institute of Child Development, University of Minnesota, 51 East River Road, Minneapolis, MN 55436. Electronic mail may be sent to mkoenig@umn.edu.

Abstract

Do children expect an expert in one domain to also be an expert in an unrelated domain? In Study 1, 32 three- and four-year-olds learned that one informant was an expert about dogs relative to another informant. When presented with pictures of new dogs or of artifacts, children who could remember which informant was the dog expert preferred her over the novice as an informant about the names of dogs, but they had no preference when the informants presented artifact labels. In Study 2, 32 children learned that one informant was incompetent about dogs whereas another was neutral. In this case, children preferred the neutral speaker over the incompetent one about both dogs and artifacts. Taken together, these results suggest that for children, expertise is not subject to a “halo effect,” but incompetence may be subject to a “pitchfork effect.”

Human culture is crucially dependent on the transmission of information from one person to another. Just as a single individual cannot possibly perform all the everyday tasks required for survival in the modern world, necessitating a division of physical labor, a single individual cannot possibly know everything required for survival in the modern world, necessitating a comparable division of cognitive labor (e.g., Keil, 2006). Depending on interest, opportunity, and ability, different people will have different pockets of expertise, and they can share that expertise when necessary. An epistemological problem, long studied by philosophers (e.g., Goldman, 1999; Hume, 1975; Plato, 2005; Putnam, 1975; Reid, 1975) concerns how a novice in a given domain determines who is qualified to provide information about that domain. As Plato (2005) asked in his dialogue Charmides, how can a layperson determine whether someone who purports to be an expert in an area really is one?

One prerequisite would seem to be recognizing that a division of cognitive labor exists in the first place, that no single individual can know everything. Although young children do sometimes act as if they believe adults are omniscient (e.g., Wimmer, Hogrefe, & Perner, 1988), Keil and his colleagues have argued that they have a nascent understanding that knowledge is not distributed equally among individuals (e.g., Danovitch & Keil, 2004; Keil, 2006; Lutz & Keil, 2002). For example, Lutz and Keil (2002) found that in a forced-choice situation, 3-year-olds could indicate that a doctor would be more likely than a car mechanic to know why people get runny noses, and that a car mechanic would be more likely than a doctor to know how to fix a flat tire. Slightly older children in that study additionally recognized that differences in expertise can be rooted at a deeper level—that a doctor would be more likely than a car mechanic to know why plants need sunlight to grow, for example, and that a car mechanic would be more likely than a doctor to know how a yo-yo works.

One important question raised by Lutz and Keil’s (2002) study—and the focus of our first study—is the extent to which children impose epistemic limits or boundaries on what they expect a given expert to know. Although children systematically selected one expert over the other when asked to choose between them in Lutz and Keil’s work, there is reason to believe that they may impute more knowledge than appropriate to a given expert when there is no obvious alternative expert available.

For example, in Taylor, Esbensen, and Bennett (1994, Study 1), preschoolers were introduced to a child who was said to know more about animals than anyone in his classroom; everyone called him an “animal expert.” When children were asked whether he would know something outside the domain of animals—how a carburetor works—4-year-olds tended to respond affirmatively, even though they denied this knowledge to themselves or to nonexpert peers. In a second, similar study, 4-year-olds also claimed that a child described as a chemistry expert would know how bird bones are different from other animals’ bones, again, even though they also said that neither they nor a nonexpert peer would know. The primary focus of these studies was on children’s understanding of knowledge acquisition rather than expertise, but Taylor et al. suggested that “our preliminary results suggest [4-year-olds] do not realize that expertise can be domain-specific” (p. 1602).

This expectation that an expert in one domain would also be knowledgeable in other domains suggests that children’s reasoning about expertise may be subject to a kind of “halo effect.” A number of studies have shown that children (and adults) often assume that an individual who has one desirable characteristic will have other desirable characteristics. For example, Cain, Heyman, and Walker (1997) found that 4- and 5-year-olds predicted that a nice child would not just be more likely than a mean child to engage in prosocial behavior; they also predicted that he or she would be smarter and more athletic (see also Benenson & Dweck, 1986; Heyman, Gee, & Giles, 2003; Stipek & Daniels, 1990; Yuill, 1997).

In our first study, we set out to investigate specifically whether children’s expectations about expertise are subject to a halo effect. Rather than pitting experts from two different domains against each other (as in Lutz & Keil, 2002), or asking yes–no questions about the knowledge of a single expert (as in Taylor et al., 1994), we presented children with an expert in one domain, along with an individual who was said to know relatively less in that domain. Children were simply asked which informant they would seek out and endorse information from—a situation that approximates the dilemma posed by Plato about how a novice can judge the knowledge of a putative expert. In one condition, the information concerned a topic squarely within the expert’s domain of expertise; in a second condition, the information concerned a topic that was unrelated. Our interest was whether children would prefer the expert informant regardless of domain (consistent with the results of Taylor et al., 1994, and the halo effect), or whether they would prefer the expert only for matters germane to his or her expertise (consistent with Lutz & Keil’s, 2002, work on children’s understanding of the division of cognitive labor).

Our procedure was derived from a recent line of work that has addressed preschoolers’ ability to track the accuracy of two potential informants (e.g., Birch, Vauthier, & Bloom, 2008; Clément, Koenig, & Harris, 2004; Jaswal, McKercher, & VanderBorght, 2008; Jaswal & Neely, 2006; Koenig, Clément, & Harris, 2004; Koenig & Harris, 2005; Pasquini, Corriveau, Koenig, & Harris, 2007; Scofield & Behrend, 2008). In these studies, 3- to 5-year-olds have preferred to learn new words from someone who has a history of having been correct about what familiar objects are called rather than someone who has been incorrect or ignorant. A subset of these studies has touched upon the scope of this preference, but this has always been in closely related domains.

For example, Koenig and Harris (2005) found that preschoolers preferred a formerly accurate labeler over a formerly ignorant one as a source for the functions of new objects. Birch et al. (2008) asked children to make inferences in the reverse direction and found that 4-year-olds preferred an informant who had been accurate about the functions of familiar objects over one who had been inaccurate when choosing which of the two would be the best source for novel object labels. Of course, knowledge about object names and object functions often do go hand-in-hand (e.g., Bloom, 2000; Kemler Nelson, Russell, Duke, & Jones, 2000), so this is perhaps not surprising. Similarly, Jaswal et al. (2008) found that preschoolers preferred a formerly accurate morphologist over an inaccurate one as the source for novel labels, but again, this may not be surprising as both concern conventional aspects of language use.

Finally, Sobel and Corriveau (2010) recently demonstrated to 4-year-olds that one informant was knowledgeable about a nonobvious internal property of a novel object (e.g., what color pin was hidden inside it) and ignorant about a nonobvious external property of the same object (e.g., what color sticker was hidden on its back), while another was knowledgeable about the external property and ignorant about the internal one. Later, children preferred the “insides” expert over the “outsides” expert as an informant about the name of the object. As Sobel and Corriveau argue, this preference is consistent with the finding that children expect an object’s insides to be relevant to its category membership, but do not have the same expectation about its outsides (e.g., Gelman, 2003). This represents another example of a situation in which the domains in which expertise generalized were closely related.

In Study 1, children learned that one individual was an expert about dogs and one was less expert about dogs. Crucially, and different from the work described above, the individual who was less expert about dogs did not commit errors, nor was she ignorant about them; she was simply less knowledgeable compared to the expert. Children in one condition chose which of the two individuals would be a better informant about the names of dogs, and children in another condition chose which would be a better informant about the names of artifacts. We chose dogs and artifacts because they represent distinct domains, and from an adult perspective, a dog expert has a very circumscribed type of knowledge.

We were not interested in the means by which children came to see the two informants as holding differential expertise about dogs, but it was important that they recognize that one was more knowledgeable about dogs than the other. Thus, we provided them with two overlapping types of evidence regarding the informants’ contrasting levels of expertise. First, the experimenter explained that one of the informants was a dog expert and knew more about dogs than anyone else (a la Taylor et al., 1994), including the other potential informant. Second, children themselves heard the dog expert refer to a series of dogs by breed names (e.g., “That’s a Sharpei dog”) whereas the other informant referred to perceptually obvious characteristics of the same dogs (e.g., “That’s a furry dog”). We thought it unlikely that children would recognize the breed names but expected that their unfamiliarity might add to the cover story that the informant who used them was especially knowledgeable about dogs—particularly when contrasted against the informant who referred to the same dogs in perceptually obvious ways.

In Study 2, we used a similar procedure to investigate the domain-specificity or generality of children’s expectations about incompetence. Just as children are more likely to confront individuals who possess pockets of expertise than general omniscience, they are also more likely to encounter people who display concise pockets of incompetence rather than an all-encompassing incompetence. To explore whether children bring domain-specific expectations to an incompetent source, we presented them with a speaker who was clearly incompetent in the limited domain of dogs. Children in Study 2 learned that one of the informants was inexperienced with dogs and knew less about dogs than anyone else, including the other informant. Next, children saw this less experienced informant refer to a series of dogs incorrectly (e.g., “That’s a Sharpei cat”) paired with an informant who made only neutral remarks (e.g., “That’s a nice one”). Our question in Study 2 was parallel to that of Study 1: Would children mistrust the incompetent source across domains or just for information regarding dogs?

Study 1

Method

Participants

Participants were sixteen 3-year-olds (mean age = 3 years 5 months [3;5], range = 3;1–3;10; 7 girls) and sixteen 4-year-olds (mean age = 4;4, range = 4;0–4;10; 8 girls). The sample was randomly selected from a database consisting of children from a Midwestern university city. Children from this pool are predominantly Caucasian, native English speakers from middle- to high-socioeconomic-status (SES) homes. An additional three children were dropped from the final sample because of parental interference or not completing the study.

Design

Children were randomly assigned to condition. Half of the children at each age participated in a dog condition, where they made judgments about which of two informants to trust about the names of dogs, and half participated in an artifact condition, where they made judgments about which of two informants to trust about the names of artifacts.

Materials

Children were presented with video clips featuring two female adult actors (one in a pink shirt and another in a blue shirt), sitting at a table. The actors were shown 8 × 10 in. color pictures of four dogs during familiarization and, depending on condition, either four additional dogs or four novel artifacts during the test phase. As will be described next, all children experienced exactly the same scaffolding, familiarization and explicit judgment trials. Depending on condition, half of the children saw the informants label dogs (dog condition) and half of the children saw the informants label artifacts (artifact condition). Hard copies of the same pictures shown to the actors were also shown to children.

Procedure

To introduce the task, the experimenter pointed to still images of the two informants and said, “I’ve got these two friends. See? One has a blue shirt and one has a pink shirt. Do you want to meet them?” The remainder of the procedure consisted of the following phases in this order: scaffolding, first explicit judgment question, familiarization, second explicit judgment question, and test trials.

Scaffolding. Children were shown two still images of the two informants on the computer screen. The experimenter pointed to each one, and explained,

Here’s my friend, Jenny, and here’s my friend, Kate. Kate is a grown up just like your mom. Jenny is a grown up just like your mom too but she knows a lot about dogs. She is an animal doctor and works with dogs all the time at the animal hospital. She knows more about dogs than anyone else I know and she knows more about dogs than Kate. All of our friends call her a dog expert because she knows so much about dogs.

For half of the participants, the pink-shirted actor was the dog expert, and for the other half, the blue-shirted actor was the dog expert.

First explicit judgment trial. Immediately following the scaffolding, the experimenter asked the first explicit judgment question, “Who knows more about dogs?” Children did not receive any feedback in response to their answers.

Familiarization. The purpose of the familiarization period was to provide children with the opportunity to observe for themselves the informants’ differential expertise about dogs. The experimenter explained,

Jenny and Kate are going to tell us about some dogs. I want you to listen very carefully to what they say and then I’m going to ask you what you think.

She began the familiarization clip, in which color photographs of four dogs of different breeds appeared, one at a time, on an easel next to the actors. One actor commented on all four pictures, and the other actor did the same. The dog expert labeled each one using subordinate breed names (e.g., “See? That’s a Basenji dog. Yep, that’s a Basenji dog”), and the novice described a perceptually obvious characteristic of the dog (e.g., “See? That’s a brown dog. Yep, that’s a brown dog”). To ensure both that the dogs were distinct and that breed names were simple and unfamiliar, the breed names did not always actually match the breed of the depicted dog. After each utterance, the experimenter paused the video and repeated what the speaker had said. Half of the participants heard the dog expert first and half heard the novice first. Table 1 shows a list of the dogs and the actors’ comments about each one.

Table 1.
Dog Pictures and Statements Made by Informants During the Familiarization Period of Studies 1 and 2
image

Second explicit judgment trial. After familiarization, the children were shown still images of the two informants and asked the explicit judgment question a second time, “Who knows more about dogs?” Again, children received no explicit feedback from the experimenter on their responses.

Test trials. In the test phase, children were shown four video clips in which the two informants made conflicting claims about four new dogs or artifacts, depending on condition. Prior to each clip being shown, the experimenter presented children with a picture of a new dog or artifact (depending on condition) and asked them to indicate which informant they would like to ask about it (hereafter, “ask” trials): “Do you know what kind of dog this is/what this is called? I bet one of these people can help. Which person would you like to ask?” (Children who claimed to know the name of an object or dog breed were told, “Actually, I don’t think that’s what it’s called” before the experimenter asked them whom they’d like to ask.) Both verbal (e.g., “Kate,”“girl in the pink shirt”) and nonverbal (i.e., pointing) responses were recorded.

After each ask trial, the experimenter started the videoclip corresponding to the novel dog or artifact the child had just been shown. In each clip, a previously unseen female actor presented one informant with the picture, and asked, “Can you tell me what this is called?” The first informant responded by saying, for example, “That’s a blicket dog” in the dog condition, or “That’s a blicket” in the artifact condition. The same question was then posed to the second informant who responded by saying, for example, “That’s a jeter [dog].” Whether the novice or expert was asked to name an item first alternated across the four clips.

After the two informants had labeled a picture, the experimenter paused the video, repeated the informants’ labels, and asked children to endorse one of the two labels (hereafter, “endorse” trials). For example, “She said it’s a blicket [dog] and she said it’s a jeter [dog]. What do you think it’s called, a blicket [dog] or a jeter [dog]?”Table 2 shows a list of the test stimuli in both conditions as well as the actors’ conflicting comments about each item.

Table 2.
Test Stimuli for Both Dog and Artifact Conditions of Studies 1 and 2
image

The entire session lasted approximately 10 min and was videotaped. Children received a point for indicating the expert for every explicit judgment and ask and endorse question.

Results

Preliminary analyses showed no differences between boys and girls, or between 3- and 4-year-olds, so we collapsed across these two variables.

Explicit Judgment Questions

Most children in both the dog and artifact conditions correctly identified the dog expert on the explicit judgment questions. After hearing the experimenter explain which of the two actors knew more about dogs, at least 14 of 16 children in each condition responded correctly when she asked them to identify the expert (EJ1). Subsequently, after observing for themselves one actor use breed names to label the dogs and the second actor describe perceptually obvious characteristics of the dogs, at least 13 of 16 children in each condition correctly identified the expert (EJ2). Most importantly for our purposes, 14 of 16 children in the artifact condition responded correctly to both explicit judgment questions, and 12 of 16 in the dog condition did so, in each case more than would be expected by chance of .25, binomial ps < .0001.

Relation Between Explicit Judgments and Test Trial Performance

As our interest was in whether an individual described as a dog expert and who had demonstrated expertise about dogs would subsequently be a preferred informant about dogs or artifacts, it was important that children actually recognize which informant was the dog expert. Thus, we focused our analyses only on the 14 children in the artifact condition and the 12 in the dog condition who answered both of the explicit judgment questions correctly.

Table 3 shows the average percentage of trials on which children indicated the dog expert as a function of age and condition. As the table shows, children in the dog condition both preferred to ask the dog expert for information about dogs and they tended to endorse the information that she provided. Combining the two types of test questions (ask and endorse) showed that children preferred the dog expert more often than expected by chance of 50% (M = 64%, SD = 21%), t(11) = 2.35, p < .05, d = .66. This is not terribly surprising, as they had just indicated that she was an expert about dogs.

Table 3.
Mean Percentage of References to the Dog Expert in Study 1 as a Function of Age, Condition, and Question Type
3-year-olds 4-year-olds Total
Dog condition (n = 12)
 Ask 45.8 (18.8) 70.8 (24.5) 58.3 (24.6)
 Endorse 70.8 (29.2) 79.2 (33.0) 75.0 (30.0)
64.3 (21.0)
Artifact condition (n = 14)
 Ask 39.3 (13.4) 46.4 (27.6) 42.8 (20.6)
 Endorse 39.3 (31.8) 50.0 (28.8) 44.6 (29.7)
43.8 (22.3)
  • Note. Only children who responded correctly to both explicit judgment questions are included. Standard deviations are in parentheses.

Crucially, however, there was no halo effect: Children in the artifact condition were as likely to ask the dog expert as the dog novice for information about artifacts and also as likely to endorse information from either. Combining the two types of test questions (ask and endorse) showed that children in this condition preferred the dog expert only at chance levels (M = 44%, SD = 22%), t(13) = 1.04, p = .32. Importantly, this chance-level performance did not reflect a bimodal distribution in which one subgroup of children systematically favored the dog expert and another systematically favored the dog novice; the ask, endorse, and combined data were each normally distributed according to Shapiro-Wilk tests of normality (ps > .05). In other words, children did not necessarily expect that a dog expert would be a better informant about artifacts than a dog novice.

A two-way analysis of variance (ANOVA; Dog/Artifact × Ask/Endorse) on the likelihood that children preferred the dog expert on test questions confirmed that children in the dog condition preferred the dog expert as an informant more often than children in the artifact condition, F(1, 24) = 7.03, p = .01, d = .95. There was no effect of question type, F(1, 24) = 2.52, p = .13, nor was there an interaction, F(1, 24) = 1.64, p = .21, indicating that this pattern was the same both when children chose whom they wanted to ask for information and whose information they would like to endorse.

Analyses at the individual level provided further evidence that children in the dog condition relied on the dog expert more often than those in the artifact condition. Because the ask and endorse questions were not independent, for this analysis, we looked at children’s responses on the endorse questions only. Whereas 9 of the 12 children in the dog condition endorsed the novel dog labels provided by the dog expert on three or more of the four test trials, just 5 of the 14 in the artifact condition endorsed the novel artifact labels provided by the dog expert on three or more of the four test trials, distributions that are marginally different from each other by a Fisher’s Exact test, p = .06.

In summary, children who systematically identified the dog expert subsequently chose to ask and endorse information from the dog expert in the dog condition only; those in the artifact condition responded randomly.

Discussion

After being exposed to the claims of an experimenter regarding who was expert and the different ways in which the two sources labeled a series of dogs, children successfully and consistently identified the person who knew more about dogs. Because children always received both types of evidence, we make no firm conclusions about whether one type of information was more powerful than another. However, it is striking to note that even though the esoteric labels used by the expert (e.g., “Basenji,”“Sharpei,”“Akita,”“Chow Chow”) presumably were not part of young children’s vocabularies, the use of these terms did not disrupt children’s appeal to the dog expert.

Our primary interest was in how children would respond when the expert and novice went on to make conflicting claims regarding new dogs and artifacts: Would they defer to the dog expert’s testimony for both artifact and dog labels in line with documented halo effects, or would they sequester their deference to the domain of expertise? Results from two types of test trial indicate that children preferred to learn dog names, but not artifact names, from dog experts. Thus, consistent with the results of Lutz and Keil’s (2002) work on the division of cognitive labor, and in contrast with previous work suggesting that children overestimate the knowledge of others (e.g., Taylor et al., 1994), even preschoolers seem to recognize that expertise in one domain does not necessarily generalize to another, unrelated domain.

In Study 2, we posed a similar question regarding the scope of children’s epistemic generalizations, but this time when one of the informants showed herself to be inexpert about dogs. Children’s mistrust of an informant may be specific to the domain in which an informant has erred in the past, just as their trust of an informant in Study 1 was specific to the domain in which the informant demonstrated expertise. Alternatively, there may be an asymmetry between expectations about competence and incompetence such that children avoid an incompetent source regardless of domain. If children think that incompetence in one domain runs the risk of occurring in other domains, children might avoid information from the inept source regarding names of both dogs and artifacts. Study 2 was designed to explore these possibilities.

Study 2

In Study 2, we used the same procedure to investigate the scope of children’s expectations about an informant who was incompetent about a particular domain. One informant was identified by the experimenter as knowing very little about dogs, and subsequently referred to each of several dogs as a “cat”; the other speaker was introduced neutrally and made neutral comments about the same dogs. If children treat a person’s incompetence as domain specific, we expect them to avoid the incompetent informant when gathering information about dogs but not when gathering information about artifacts. If they treat incompetence as domain general, then they should avoid the incompetent informant in both cases.

Method

Participants

Participants were sixteen 3-year-olds (mean age = 3;6, range = 3;0–3;11; 9 girls) and sixteen 4-year-olds (mean age = 4;5, range = 4;1–4;11; 8 girls). The sample was randomly selected from the same database as the first study. No child had participated in Study 1.

Design and Procedure

Study 2 incorporated the same stimuli and basic procedure as Study 1. As in Study 1, all children experienced the same scaffolding, familiarization, and explicit judgment trials. Only the test stimuli differed between the two conditions. Specifically, half of the children at each age saw the informants label dogs (dog condition) and half of the children saw the informants label artifacts (artifact condition). The focal difference between the Study 1 and Study 2 was that children in Study 2 were presented with an informant who was said to be inexperienced about dogs and shown to be inept about them, along with a second informant whose level of dog knowledge was left unspecified. This manipulation led to procedural differences from Study 1 in the scaffolding, explicit judgment questions and familiarization phase which we describe next.

Scaffolding. Children were shown two still images of the two informants on the computer screen. The experimenter pointed to each one and explained,

Here’s my friend, Jenny, and here’s my friend, Kate. Kate is a grown up just like your mom. Jenny is a grown up just like your mom too but Jenny does not know much about dogs. Jenny spends time with other kinds of animals but when she was a girl, Jenny didn’t have any dogs and she doesn’t have any now either. Jenny knows less about dogs than anyone else I know and Jenny knows much less about dogs than Kate. All of our friends say that Jenny doesn’t know anything about dogs.

For half of the participants, the pink-shirted actor was said to be inexpert about dogs, and for the other half, the blue-shirted actor was the nonexpert.

First explicit judgment trial. The experimenter then asked the first explicit judgment question, “Who does not know much about dogs?” Children received no explicit feedback in response to their answers.

Familiarization. As in Study 1, the experimenter then explained,

Now Jenny and Kate are going to tell us about some dogs. I want you to listen very carefully to what they say and then I’m going to ask you what you think.

She began the familiarization clip, in which the same color photographs of four dogs used in Study 1 appeared, one at a time, on an easel next to the actors. One actor commented on all four pictures, and then the other actor did the same. The nonexpert labeled each one using the breed names from Study 1 but crucially, mislabeled each animal as a cat (e.g., “See? That’s a Basenji cat. Yep, that’s a Basenji cat”).

The other informant referred to the same pictures in a neutral manner (e.g., “See? That’s a nice one. Yep, I like that one”). The neutral comments were worded in this manner so as to provide the children with no information that could be used to evaluate the neutral speaker’s competence or incompetence. If we had used the same comments as in Study 1 (i.e., perceptually obvious comments, such as “That’s a furry dog”), the neutral speaker would have been correct and the inexpert incorrect; by simply referring to each dog as “nice” in the current study, the neutral speaker’s comments could not be judged to be correct or incorrect whereas the inexpert was clearly wrong. (Indeed, the lack of variation in the neutral speaker’s comments across the four dogs during familiarization could suggest that she was not paying very close attention to them.) After each utterance, the experimenter paused the video and repeated what the speaker had said. Half of the participants heard the nonexpert first and half heard the neutral informant first. Table 1 shows a list of the dogs and the actors’ comments about each one.

Second explicit judgment trial. Children were shown still images of the two informants and asked the explicit judgment question a second time, “Who does not know much about dogs?” Again, children received no explicit feedback from the experimenter on their responses.

Test trials. Test trials were identical to those in Study 1 (see Table 2).

Results

Again, preliminary analyses showed no differences between boys and girls, or between 3- and 4-year-olds, so we collapsed across these two variables.

Explicit Judgment Questions

Most children in both the dog and artifact conditions correctly identified the nonexpert on the explicit judgment questions. After hearing the experimenter explain which of the two actors knew less about dogs, at least 14 of 16 children in each condition responded correctly when she asked them “who does not know much about dogs” (EJ1). Subsequently, after observing for themselves one actor mislabel dogs as “cats” and the second actor make nondescriptive neutral comments during familiarization, 14 of 16 children in each condition correctly identified the nonexpert (EJ2). Most importantly for our purposes, 14 of 16 children in the dog condition responded correctly to both explicit judgment questions, and 13 of 16 in the artifact condition did so, in each case more than would be expected by chance of .25, binomial ps < .0001.

Relation Between Explicit Judgments and Test Trial Performance

Our interest in Study 2 was in whether an individual who was inexpert about a given domain would be treated as universally inexpert. Thus, it was important that children actually recognize which informant was inexpert, so we focused our analyses on the 13 children in the artifact condition and the 14 in the dog condition who answered both of the explicit judgment questions correctly.

As Table 4 shows, children in both conditions avoided the informant who had been incompetent about dogs. That is, whether they were seeking or endorsing information about dogs or about artifacts, children preferred the neutral informant—in both cases, more than would be expected by chance of 50%: dog condition (M = 65%, SD = 17%), t(13) = 3.32, p < .01, d = .71, and artifact condition (M = 67%, SD = 22%), t(12) = 2.84, p < .02, d = .77. Whereas an expectation about expertise was domain specific in Study 1, an expectation about incompetence proved to be domain general.

Table 4.
Mean Percentage of References to the Neutral Informant in Study 2 as a Function of Age, Condition, and Question Type
3-year-olds 4-year-olds Total
Dog condition (n = 14)
 Ask 65.6 (26.5) 58.3 (12.9) 62.5 (21.4)
 Endorse 68.7 (25.8) 62.5 (20.9) 66.1 (23.2)
65.2 (17.1)
Artifact condition (n = 13)
 Ask 45.8 (29.2) 71.4 (22.4) 59.6 (28.0)
 Endorse 70.8 (18.8) 78.6 (30.3) 75.0 (25.0)
67.3 (21.9)
  • Note. Only children who responded correctly to both explicit judgment questions are included. Standard deviations are in parentheses.

A two-way ANOVA (Dog/Artifact × Ask/Endorse) confirmed that children preferred the neutral informant to the same extent in both conditions, F(1, 25) = 0.08, ns. There was a tendency for children to show a greater preference for the neutral informant on endorse trials than on ask trials (71% vs. 61%), but this was not quite significant, F(1, 25) = 3.94, p = .06, d = .41. There was no interaction, F(1, 25) = 0.92, p = .35.

Analyses at the individual level provided further evidence that children relied on the neutral informant to the same extent in both the dog and the artifact conditions. As in Study 1, because responses on the ask and endorse questions were not independent, this analysis focused on children’s responses on the endorse questions only. Eight of the 14 children in the dog condition endorsed the novel dog labels from the neutral informant on three or more of the four test trials, and 11 of the 13 children in the artifact condition endorsed the novel artifact labels from the neutral informant on three or more of the test trials, distributions that do not differ from each other by Fisher’s Exact test, p = .20.

Discussion

Children who could identify the informant who did not know much about dogs subsequently preferred the neutral informant for both dog and artifact labels. This preference for the neutral informant was not due to children’s evaluations of her prior accuracy or knowledge: During the familiarization phase, the neutral informant made comments about dogs that could not be evaluated for accuracy. Thus, children were avoiding the informant who was inexpert about dogs even if only to favor a weak or unmarked informant. In contrast to the domain-specific trust of experts in Study 1, when someone was found to be incompetent, children avoided her across domains.

It is important to emphasize that during the familiarization phase, the incompetent informant was described as and was demonstrated to be incompetent within the circumscribed domain of dogs. Although the errors she made were obvious (e.g., referring to a dog as a “Basenji cat”), they were bounded because they were all in a particular domain, and they were not implausible insofar as referring to a dog as a “cat” represents a taxonomically related overextension. Indeed, the errors in Study 2 were arguably more plausible than errors used in other research on reliability (e.g., Jaswal & Neely, 2006; Koenig et al., 2004). Given this, it is still important to acknowledge that incompetence is one of several inferences children could conceivably make about someone who produces mistaken utterances. Despite the evidence that these labeling errors were limited to a particular domain in the current study, children avoided the incompetent informant across domains.

Study 1 Versus Study 2 Comparison

We compared children’s preference for the dog expert in Study 1 to their preference for the neutral informant in Study 2. Although cross-study comparisons must be interpreted cautiously, given that the two studies made use of the same stimulus materials, counterbalancing, general procedure, and test questions, we felt such a comparison was warranted and could be informative.

Using only those children in the studies who passed both explicit judgment questions, we conducted a 2 × 2 ANOVA (Study 1/Study 2 × Dog/Artifact) on the likelihood that children preferred the dog expert (for Study 1 participants) or the neutral informant (for Study 2 participants). The reason for comparing children’s preference of these two informants is that they were the ones preferred in the dog condition of each study, and our interest was in comparing whether that preference was maintained in the artifact condition of each study. Children in Study 2 were more likely to have a preference for one of the two informants overall than children in Study 1, F(1, 49) = 4.96, p < .04, d = .59. However, this main effect must be considered in light of a significant interaction between study and condition, F(1, 49) = 3.91, p = .05. The interaction reflects the fact that children in Study 1 preferred the dog expert for information about dogs on an average of 64% of test trials, and children in Study 2 preferred the neutral informant for information about dogs 65% of the time. In contrast, children in Study 1 preferred the dog expert for information about artifacts on an average of just 44% of test trials, whereas children in Study 2 continued to have a preference for the neutral informant for information about artifacts—on an average of 67% of test trials. There was no main effect of condition, F(1, 49) = 2.55, p = .117.

General Discussion

Our goals were, first, to investigate whether children expect an expert in one domain to be an expert in an unrelated domain and, second, whether children expect an incompetent source to be incompetent in an unrelated domain. Study 1 demonstrated that children do not expect expertise to generalize to an unrelated domain. They preferred a dog expert over a dog novice when it came to the names of dogs but showed no preference when it came to the names of artifacts. In contrast, results of Study 2 suggest that children do expect incompetence to generalize across unrelated domains. Regardless of whether the task involved the names of dogs or artifacts, they preferred a neutral informant over one who was said to be inexperienced with and had demonstrated incompetence about dogs. In other words, children gave a domain-specific treatment to expertise and a domain-general treatment to incompetence. We next consider three important implications of these findings.

Study 1’s results suggesting that expertise may be domain specific are consistent with the results from Lutz and Keil’s (2002) work on the division of cognitive labor, but they stand in contrast to many demonstrations of a “halo effect” in the developmental literature. In these studies, children have been shown to make global judgments of others’ abilities: If a person is known to be highly ranked in one domain, they expect that he or she is also highly ranked in other domains (Benenson & Dweck, 1986; Cain et al., 1997; Miller, 2000). In fact, at the youngest ages, the domains need not be closely related: being smart may be associated with being nice and perhaps being a fast runner as well (Droege & Stipek, 1993; Heyman et al., 2003; Stipek & Daniels, 1990; Yuill, 1997).

Our failure to find a halo effect seems most at odds with the findings of Taylor et al. (1994). In that study, 4-year-olds often credited an acknowledged expert in one domain (e.g., a “chemistry expert”) with special knowledge in another domain (e.g., how bird bones differ from other animals’ bones). There are at least two methodological differences between the studies that could help to explain these conflicting results. First, the primary emphasis of Taylor et al.’s study was on children’s understanding of knowledge acquisition; the single yes–no question about expertise was a minor part of their project, resulting in what they acknowledged were “preliminary results” (p. 1602). In contrast, we assessed children’s expectations about expertise on eight trials (four ask and four endorse; statistically, there was no difference between the two types of test trials). This allowed us to compare children’s performance to chance, across conditions, and to conduct analyses by individual. In each case, we found differences between the dog condition and the artifact condition in Study 1, which suggested that children’s expectations about expertise are domain specific.

A second methodological difference between the two studies is that the domain of acknowledged expertise in our Study 1 was lower in the taxonomic hierarchy than the domains used by Taylor et al. (1994). Specifically, Study 1 used an expert about dogs, whereas Taylor et al. used an “animal expert” or “chemistry expert.” Perhaps 3- and 4-year-olds expect a subordinate or basic level expert to have less knowledge than experts at a higher level. If our expert had been an animal expert, perhaps children would have had broader expectations about the scope of her expertise. This remains an intriguing question for future work.

Although we found no evidence in Study 1 of a halo effect for expertise, Study 2 suggested a “pitchfork effect” for incompetence. Someone who was clearly incompetent about dogs was avoided not just when it came to dogs, but also when it came to artifacts. We suggest that the difference in the domain generality of expertise and incompetence may be related to a general psychological phenomenon widely studied among adults, known as a “negativity bias” or a “positive–negative asymmetry” (Baumeister, Bratslavsky, Finkenauer & Vohs, 2001; Vaish, Grossman, & Woodward, 2008). In the adult literature on impression formation, one common finding is that negative information about a person or a new acquaintance generally carries more weight than good information about a person (e.g., Peeters & Czapinski, 1990).

For example, when college students were asked to judge the likability of a target person who was said to perform a series of both negative and positive behaviors (he or she ordered the most expensive drink when someone else bought a round but also purchased groceries for an ill neighbor), negative behaviors were weighted more heavily (Vonk, 1996; see also Fiske, 1980; Vonk, 1999). Similarly, children require fewer examples of negative behaviors to infer negative traits about other people than they do positive behaviors to infer positive traits (e.g., Aloise, 1993), and their memory for individuals who have done negative things (e.g., stolen the class’s cookies) is better than their memory for individuals who have done positive things (e.g., brought in cookies for the class; Kinzler & Shutts, 2008).

Our studies seem consistent with this negativity bias in that information, suggesting that a particular individual was incompetent in one domain (i.e., “bad”) readily led to a global evaluation of that individual as incompetent, but information suggesting that a particular source was knowledgeable (i.e., “good”) in one domain did not lead to a global evaluation of that source as especially knowledgeable across domains. Although the “negativity bias” has been recently emphasized, specifically in early emotional development (Vaish et al., 2008), the possibility of a cognitive or epistemic negativity bias seems reasonable given the nonemotional cases of the bias in adult memory, information processing, social learning, stereotyping, and neurological processing (for a review of the adult literature, see Baumeister, Bratlavsky, Finkenauer, & Vohs, 2001).

As noted in the Introduction, a few previous studies using the reliability paradigm have found that children’s preference for one informant over another generalized from one domain to another closely related one (e.g., names to functions, internal properties to labels; Birch et al., 2008; Koenig & Harris, 2005; Sobel & Corriveau, 2010). In each of these studies, one informant demonstrated reliability in a particular domain, whereas the other informant was either inaccurate or ignorant in that domain. It is not clear from these studies whether children were preferring the more reliable source, or avoiding the inaccurate or ignorant person. Our findings may help to shed some light on this question.

Specifically, in our studies, one informant demonstrated expertise or incompetence in a particular domain, whereas the other informant was merely neutral. (Note that this is different from the work just described, where the other informant was always inaccurate or ignorant.) Children preferred the expert over the neutral informant in the domain of the expert’s expertise, but not in a different domain (Study 1), and they avoided the incompetent individual in favor of the neutral one both in the domain in which the incompetent one demonstrated incompetence and in a different domain (Study 2). Thus, the generalization from names to functions (or functions to names) or insides to names in the previous work may reflect the fact that children have a relatively undifferentiated mistrust of speakers who have been inaccurate or ignorant, not that they have an undifferentiated trust of those who have been competent. The implication of this (along with the negativity bias described earlier) is that when reasoning about how trustworthy someone is, examples of when they have been wrong may be weighted more heavily than examples of when they have been right.

Indeed, in Corriveau, Meints, and Harris (2009), 3-year-olds treated a previously accurate informant and a previously neutral one as equally good informants, suggesting that being accurate did not confer any special status on a potential informant when the alternative was someone who had been neutral. Furthermore, in Pasquini et al. (2007), 3-year-olds consistently avoided an informant who had been wrong, even if that individual had erred just once in the past. We suggest that young children may not form impressions of someone’s trustworthiness (and perhaps a host of other traits as well) by adding up and averaging all of the information they have about that person, good and bad alike. Instead, like adults, negative information may have stronger effects on their final impressions. Given children’s early sensitivity to negative information and to inaccuracy in particular (Koenig & Woodward, 2010), it seems possible that children younger than the 3- and 4-year-olds tested here might also show an asymmetry in which incompetence generalizes to other domains, but competence does not.

As noted in the Introduction, we were not concerned with the means by which children came to recognize the differential dog knowledge of the two informants in the present work—the scaffolding, the observations, or some combination of the two. Our goal in this initial investigation was to understand whether they expected an individual’s expertise or incompetence in a particular domain to be limited to that domain, or to generalize across domains. The possibility that children treated the subordinate breed names as a piece of evidence in favor of a speaker’s expertise deserves further attention. Thus, an important question for future work will be to investigate precisely the circumstances that lead children to recognize differences in expertise.

Other questions that emerge from these experiments concern delineating the scope of children’s attributions and the way they may change with development. For example, children’s deference to the dog expert in Study 1, though systematic and unique to dog information, was not at ceiling levels. If children’s appeal to the expert becomes more marked with age, it is possible that halo effects could emerge with development. Furthermore, children in Study 1 might have preferred the dog expert if the test questions had been about a more scientific domain or a distinct animal species. Children may appreciate that dog expertise does not reach far enough to encompass everyday artifacts, but they may believe that it encompasses other, less distally related things (e.g., sharks, insects, people, etc.; Keil, Stein, Webb, Billings, & Rozenblit, 2008; Lutz & Keil, 2002).

In conclusion, results from Study 1 suggest that there is no halo effect for children’s expectations about expertise: An expert in one narrow domain is not necessarily especially knowledgeable in another, unrelated domain. However, results from Study 2 point toward a pitchfork effect for children’s expectations about incompetence: Someone who is clearly incompetent in one narrow domain is avoided not just as a source in that domain but also in another, unrelated one.