Examining the ethical environment in higher education
Abstract
Higher Education Institutions (HEIs) across the world have found themselves faced with new challenges on issues of ethics. Much of this has been centred on issues of assessment: plagiarism, buying essays, sharing/lending of previously passed work and the stealing of marked/returned work of others. Institutions still treat academic misconduct as largely a behavioural difficulty rather than an issue of ethics (or education), suggesting that academia places a far greater emphasis on combating new forms of dishonesty than it does on encouraging ethical habits and a healthy ethical environment. To date, the majority of research in this area has examined these forms of academic misconduct from the point of view of the student and/or the university, with the perspective of academics receiving very limited attention. Our hypothesis is that academics are perhaps best placed to provide the education needed to create and sustain an ethical environment, and we argue that being ‘ethically aware’ is a critical factor in the development of academic competence for all parties. This study adds to existing research in three ways: firstly, by highlighting the importance of an overall framework for an ethical environment within HEIs; secondly, by suggesting an ecological model of key parties (the university, students and academics) with responsibility for this environment in assessment; and thirdly, by including new evidence (generated by a survey of academics) to extend our understanding of their views on these issues.
Introduction
In March 2017, 270 final year medical students at the University of Glasgow were told that they would have to retake their end-of-course practical assessment after purported online collusion. Students who had taken the tests early reportedly used social media to discuss the scenarios faced for the benefit of those who had yet to take the assessment. (Bodkin, 2017)1
A veritable tsunami of issues have come together in recent years to challenge previously held principles on systemic integrity in Higher Education Institutions (HEIs) across much of the western world. This is exemplified by the shrinking employment possibilities for those without a university degree; the ‘high-stakes testing’ of secondary education feeding in to the commodification of higher degrees; the enormous financial burden students face for studying; and the positioning of students as customers or consumers, whose interactions are governed by contracts. Universities have always faced some ethical challenges, such as academics falsifying research data or students stealing exam papers in advance of a test, but concerns about these practices have been heightened by the high-stakes nature of a university education, such as: the sharing of confidential assessment data in online environments (see Bodkin, 2017), plagiarism, buying essays, covert sharing/lending of work and the stealing of marked/returned work.
The paucity of an overall account within which these issues can be framed often leaves researchers unable to connect with the ethical values that underpin what is claimed to be ‘the war against academic dishonesty’ (Zwagerman, 2008: 676). Institutions still treat academic misconduct as largely a behavioural difficulty rather than an issue of ethics (or education) (Allen et al., 1998), suggesting that academia places a far greater emphasis on combating new forms of dishonesty than it does on encouraging ethical habits and a healthy ethical environment. This could give the impression that universities are simply fire-fighting outbreaks of academic dishonesty as the sole means of sustaining the ethical environment of assessment. In reality, they are attempting to do much more.
We propose that a healthy ethical environment is needed for academia to function and to maintain its values, and it is often the voices of academics that can play a crucial part in this ethical milieu. We believe that acting ethically goes beyond avoiding plagiarism, correct referencing and stylistic approaches to academic writing. It can raise uncomfortable questions as to just how students might be encouraged to develop the values underpinning academic integrity and consequently, how academics ensure that they abide by this without creating a punitive atmosphere.
This article explores the ethical environment of the university, drawing links to the existing literature to support a triadic model of the ecology. This study makes an important contribution to existing research in three ways: firstly, by providing an overall framework in which to position existing research—the ethical environment; secondly, by suggesting a triadic ecological model of the major parties with responsibility for this environment in assessment—the university, the students and the academics; thirdly, by incorporating data from research with academics in the UK context.2
Understanding the ethical environment
To date, there has been scant philosophical attention paid to the use of ecological models as a way of understanding ethical issues, despite their wide usage in medicine, psychology and the humanities (Hogue, 1984; Warren & Cheney, 1991; Visser, 2007). Yet these models are often distinguished by the ways in which they bring together both policy and practice: for example, codes, regulations, rules, the physical environment and intrapersonal issues (Sallis & Sallis, 1988). Because of this, we adopted the metaphor of an ecology in order to explore the intrapersonal relationships that provide the protection of the overall environment. Many of these form frameworks for studying particular issues/problems in a multidimensional way, with attention focused on a wide variety of explanations. This metaphor may prove a suitable lens through which to examine assessment in the overall ethical environment of the university.
Ecological models have proved to be helpful for examining issues that might have previously been perceived as separate parts of an ethical landscape (McCarthy, 2012). Previous research in this area claims that such approaches provide a more holistic view of the issues and extend the analysis to consider the consequences (Raisner, 1997; Meyers, 2004). Indeed, Raisner (1997) argues that such approaches allow us to go beyond systems of ethics and good/bad behaviour to focus on dealing with the practical problems invoked in such debates.
Most discussions of the ‘environment’ tend to emphasise a physical environment; other common uses highlight social interactions through studying the social environment. So, what exactly do we mean by an ethical environment? First, we are not using the term ‘ethical’ environment as a way of distinguishing it from an unethical environment but as a way to establish characteristics that define its reach. Second, we wish to distinguish this from other similar concepts such as ethos, atmosphere,3 ethical climate, or even beliefs and ideas about social relationships and interactions. Third, values are embedded in both the practices and institutions that adopt them and are essential for their proper functioning. But these need not always be the same values as held by those who work there. By studying the overall landscape, considering how universities, students and staff conceptualise their values and attitudes, we intend to reveal a discrete ethical ecology working in this area.
… the ethical environment is always there; we cannot live outside of it. Particular individuals may ignore particular aspects of it—someone might for instance be indifferent to moral notions in the narrow sense… but the same person will still live in an environment of ideas about how to live, what is important and so on.
Haydon (2004) suggests that there could be a multiplicity of ethical environments that interact with one another, and this opens up the possibility of the university as having a particular ethical environment that is unique to its situation, but still forms part of a larger overall ethical environment.
Providing a strong ethical environment that promotes ethical decision-making often comprises a plethora of beliefs and expectations, of ideologies and values, attitudes and norms (Dalton & Radtke, 2013; Arnold et al., 2000). Evaluating the health of this environment involves considering the issues from the stance of all participants in the ecology: in this case, the institution, the students and the academics. Failure to accommodate any one group could potentially create a weakness, not only within the ecology, but across the whole ethical environment. As Haydon (2006) cautions, it is often a lack of clarity around our understanding of rules and responsibilities that can lead to an erosion of the ethical environment. A key factor in this is what institutions and academic staff say they value and what they actually enact in terms of assessment: policies can only have effective value when they match the actions of those using them. This means that in order to study the ethical environment, one would need to look at the overall organisational culture and the behaviour of those who work there (Meyers, 2004; Arnold et al., 2000).
Responsibility for upholding the wider ethical environment of HEIs is often devolved to the academic staff and students. Other actors, for example administrators or librarians, within HEIs may have an impact on the ethical environment too. Similarly, it is important to note that unethical behaviour is not solely the domain of students; the university and academic staff may also act unethically on occasions, yet it is student misdemeanours that still merit widespread attention in both research and policy.
The university
Universities across the world no longer function simply as repositories of knowledge, nor as communities of scholars. The swift transition from elite to mass education, and the increased marketisation of higher education in recent decades, has diluted Newman's classic account of the university (Newman & Turner, 1996). This transition reframes what historically has been accepted by communities of scholars as a distinct set of values existing within universities; a realignment has taken place seeking to bring them more in line with the dominant values across broader society. Whilst the particular values of the university originally evolved from a distinct sense of purpose of what a university was, as Collini (2012) notes, this purpose is now challenged and lacks clarity. Similarly, Oakeshott's conceptualisation of the university as an ‘interval’ in life (for the undergraduate) in which to learn to live a more ‘significant’ life also depicts a world that seems to be receding (Oakeshott, 2004). The emphasis on graduate employability and the marketisation of higher education reframes this ideal into highly utilitarian functions, whereby the ‘good life’ for students is now characterised by access to desired and desirable professions and jobs (Dore, 1979; Love, 2008; Tomlinson, 2010).
Much of the current literature focused on ethical behaviour in universities still identifies what we term the ‘big three’ as being of significant concern: plagiarism, cheating and fraud (Dowling, 2003; Brown & McInerney, 2008; Coren, 2012). Research by Nijhof et al. (2012) suggests two ways in which HEIs generally address these problems. First, by having formal ethical policies and employing personnel charged with upholding institutional ethics in daily decision and policy-making practices. Second, the willingness of institutions’ management to uphold such an ethos and culture. These two approaches are sometimes described as preventing unethical behaviour (compliance) and promoting ethical behaviour (education).
Compliance
Compliance-based approaches emphasise programmes designed to ‘prevent, detect and punish violations of pre-set standards of behaviour, especially in the area of law and organisational norms’ (Nijhof et al., 2012: 98). Theorists such as Howard (2004) critique this approach as being somewhat reductive, in that we risk seeing all students as ‘would-be criminals’ and our role as academics as ‘policing’ them. Perhaps more importantly, it may give the simplistic impression that by avoiding particular identified activities, a healthier ethical environment is automatically sustained.
Globally, HEIs achieve compliance by reference to general codes of conduct, disciplinary systems or codes of ethics that can be applied to both students and/or employees. Such regulations are often given a privileged status by institutionalising a conception of acceptable behaviour, outlining what is not acceptable and listing the subsequent penalties. Whilst codes and policies tend to be freely available to students, they are often written in highly legalistic language, so it is perhaps unsurprising that students often struggle to understand them. Whilst research suggests that a lack of understanding may be associated with high levels of dishonesty (McCabe & Trevino, 1993), classifying such behaviour as ‘dishonest’ can be problematic; ignorance of policies and regulations does not necessarily lead to acting with the intent to deceive.
Codes can undoubtedly help clarify ethical thinking for some, and serve to educate a targeted population in desired standards of behaviour. There are merits to such systems: for example, having a code can have a positive impact on perceptions of ethical behaviour, even when users might not recall specific aspects of it (McCabe & Trevino, 1996; Adams et al., 2001; McCabe et al., 2002). Similarly, having a code can be useful for having something to refer students to when troublesome issues arise (Auger, 2013), but codes are not always the best way to address ethical issues. Formal codes cannot cover all situations that might arise, and this can leave universities trying to address new types of misconduct—particularly those using new technologies—without adequate policies. Codes can also institutionalise an approach to ethics (Small, 2001) and in a university context, this risks staff and students becoming less able to think and act independently in new situations, or where it is unclear how the rules might apply.
Education
Whilst the prevalence and scope of academic unethical behaviour amongst students has long been studied and reported (McCabe, 2001; Malgwi & Rakovski, 2009), the same attention has not always been given to educating for or inculcating a sense of ethical integrity in students. Some disciplines (e.g. business, law, medicine and journalism) include ethics within their curricula because it is felt to be important that their students are taught how to think ethically in order to influence ethical actions (Spain & Robles, 2011; Lavine & Roussin, 2012; Trautner & Borland, 2013). A common principle of such programmes is that ethics and personal integrity are at the heart of the normative description of ourselves as moral actors; that there are moral and ethical dimensions fundamental to social responsibility and to the professional identity of people in those professions.
The ethical environment: Students
Over a decade ago, Westacott (2008) suggested that the growth of academic dishonesty in assessment processes was symptomatic of the approach students were encouraged to take to cope with a strictly instrumental view of education. This chimes with the UK experience, in which concerns are often voiced in terms that ‘students seek to secure a degree, rather than experience an education, with their goals limited to the acquisition of skills needed for employment and maximizing income’ (Natale & Doran, 2012: 188). In recent years, universities have emphasised post-graduation employability and skills with the expectation that these will be embedded into taught modules. However, such an approach can encourage students to see higher education as strictly a financial investment with expectations of a guaranteed return. Yet such instrumentality can be an unwitting failure on the part of universities to adequately induct students into the relevant part of the ethical environment and hence requires serious consideration.
To date, a tranche of research has examined academic misconduct from the point of view of the student (Malgwi & Rakovski, 2009; Smyth et al., 2009; Comas-Forgas & Sureda-Negre, 2010). We have evidence for why students cheat (Malgwi & Rakovski, 2009), how they cheat (Comas-Forgas & Sureda-Negre, 2010), when they cheat (McCabe & Trevino, 1996; Walker, 2010), where they do it (McLafferty & Foust, 2004) and how they justify it (Molnar & Kletke, 2012). As the use of plagiarism detection software (such as Turnitin) has become more widespread in HEIs, students know that they can no longer simply cut and paste information from the internet. However, Walker (2010) suggests an alternative interpretation of such events: that the use of such software may just have encouraged students to become better at cheating. Counterintuitively, he found that novice students plagiarised less than those in their final year, suggesting that some students actually refined their methods of cheating as they progressed. Similarly, research by Molnar and Kletke (2012: 211) found that over time: ‘… students are more willing to cheat and increasingly less concerned about doing so’. However, they suggested that students perceived plagiarism in a different way to other types of cheating; that stealing a handbag was unacceptable, but stealing words was not viewed in the same way.
This tension between compliance and education within institutional demands seems to have no obvious answer. Löfström (2011: 259) makes the point that because universities frequently overemphasise the avoidance of plagiarism, students fail to grasp the reasoning behind key academic writing: ‘… and consequently do not comprehend the underlying functions of proper citation and referencing as they pertain to advancing knowledge in the field’. This leads us to conclude that students may need on-going education to appreciate just why particular practices are ethically significant4 in order to play their part in the upholding of the ethical environment.
The ethical environment: Academics
Whilst the professional identity of academics is well established in research (see e.g. Gordon & Whitchurch, 2010), this tends to focus on individuals’ perceptions of their role as a teacher rather than any responsibility for their part in this. We know more about student behaviour than we do about institutional compliance practices; we know far more about such practices than we do about the views of academics. Yet this lack of ‘academic voice’ can unintentionally leave a weakness in creating an ecology capable of supporting the ethical environment covering assessment in HEIs. For example, Nuss (1984) found that over half of the faculty questioned said that they rarely discussed university policies or their educative responsibilities concerning academic dishonesty with their students. More recent research tentatively suggests that compliance and education are ‘two sides of the same coin’, and that such discussions should be essential to ensure students understand key codes and regulations (Zwagerman, 2008; Baker, 2013).
Sustaining an ethical environment is complex, and communicating these values and commitments to others can be difficult and even unpleasant. For example, codes need to be reinforced by surveillance and action in order to be effective. It is not enough for academics simply to disapprove of a student's cheating behaviour; they need to actively confront it, regardless of how uncomfortable they may feel about this (Hard et al., 2006; Hutton, 2006). Failure by staff to do this may lead students to believe that they can get away with deception, thus increasing the overall frequency of such behaviours (Hard et al., 2006).
This study is a starting point for considering how assessment is situated within the construct of a broader ethical environment in education. We believe that where academics are unwilling to play their part, the overall ethical environment of the university is undermined and this has the potential to damage both assessment practice and public trust in the whole system. Approaching such fundamental ethical considerations can involve sensitive discussions with academic peers in order to elicit their views.
Method
The research reported here attempts to reframe how academics think about assessment as an integral aspect of the ecologies that exist within the concept of an ethical environment of an HEI. Three research questions guided the exploratory empirical research:
- How can we conceptualise the ethical environment of assessment in higher education?
- What sustains this environment?
- How do academics understand their role within the ethical environment?
To explore these questions, we designed an anonymous questionnaire survey that allowed respondents to comment freely on what may be considered sensitive issues. Given that this research is exploratory in nature and received no funding, we urge caution over assuming any generalisability due to the small numbers of participants involved. The samples were necessarily small as this study was (a) investigatory and (b) limited due to stipulations from the HEI ethical clearance agreements given for such work. We have limited our ecology to three groups (the university, the faculty and the students), to examine our hypothesis that academics are best placed to provide the education needed for compliance. This is not to say that they do this alone; student services, academic support staff and librarians—amongst others—are important contributors.
Data collection tools were piloted, adjusted and a final copy set up with an email link sent out to prospective respondents. We recruited participants via a snowball sampling technique (Bailey, 1994); there were several reasons for adopting this methodology. First, snowball sampling is a well-known technique for inquiry into sensitive or ethical topics (Faugier & Sargeant, 1997; Penrod et al., 2003; Noy, 2008). Second, snowball sampling can be an effective tool for targeting populations (e.g. academics) that are defined by their activities (Sudman & Kalton, 1986). Whilst the technique is sometimes criticised as only drawing from ‘people like us’ (Biernacki & Waldorf, 1981; Penrod et al., 2003), we viewed this as a strength; we wanted to recruit other, similar academics and only from this category. The third reason was purely pragmatic; in order to secure ethical clearance, we needed a technique that ensured a complete separation of the researcher from those being researched.
The software application Survey Monkey5 was used to produce an online survey comprising both open and closed questions relating to respondents’ work history and attitudes to teaching and learning. The survey included three assessment-related case studies (see Table 1) and respondents were invited to comment on each one. To meet word limits, the cases have been summarised here.
Case 1 | Twenty students were offered the opportunity to receive feedback on a piece of work each week; they could hand this in at the lecture and receive online feedback via the VLE. Feedback for all students was typed up into one Word document and uploaded onto a VLE with student ID anonymised (the original work was kept by the lecturer). One student, Joe, realised that he could read the feedback for everyone but did not need to contribute any writing himself. In week three, Joe stopped contributing writing but continued reading the feedback. When it came to the assignment, he read the feedback for others and applied it to his own work. |
Case 2 | A course for third-year undergraduate students is assessed by a group project. Using the VLE, students must contribute to blog discussions and then use these interactions as the basis for a group report. At the end of the course, the blogs and the report are assessed and each group is given a grade. The tutor then tells the students that they have to apportion the grade appropriate to each group member's contributions to the online and written tasks. |
Case 3 | Students are asked to individually research and prepare for a seminar presentation using a PowerPoint and a handout. One student presents an image and text which you know belong to another author but remain unreferenced throughout the student's presentation. The written work has to be uploaded via the anti-plagiarism software checking site and your suspicions are confirmed. When you challenge the student on this source, they claim the work is presented on a generic website (which they have referenced) and use of small amounts of text is acceptable. |
Data
The survey invitation was sent to 102 academics and 33 completed it; of these, 31 were either currently working or had worked in universities. Due to the small numbers involved in the study, it was not viable to conduct any tests for significance, but the data were summarised using descriptive statistics.
Questions 1–4 asked respondents about their employment experience; they comprised senior/lecturers (n = 14), professors (n = 11) and principal lecturers, readers, teaching fellows and one academic developer (n = 8). Almost half (n = 15) of our respondents had worked in higher education for 16 years or more and only three had worked for 5 years or less in this sector. Most respondents (n = 25) indicated that teaching formed more than 50% of their workload, and 13 said that research formed over half of their workload. Four people had teaching-only contracts, three taught both undergraduate and postgraduate students, and one was a school experience tutor.
Most HEI assessment now takes place within virtual learning environments (VLEs), so questions 5–8 focused on the participants’ use and knowledge of these. The majority of respondents (n = 28) had used a VLE and of these, 17 had used it for a range of assessment purposes (see Table 2).
Response count | |
---|---|
Providing online feedback | 14 |
Grading and marking | 14 |
Blogging | 5 |
Practice tests | 2 |
Revision quizzes | 2 |
Other (please specify) | 0 |
We were interested in the use of VLEs to check for plagiarism (as one of our ‘big three’) and in particular, the ways in which academics felt they had responsibility for this seemingly technical process. Table 3 summarises the results.
Answer options | Response count |
---|---|
Check every submission | 16 |
Check a small sample (5–10%) | 6 |
Check before marking | 11 |
Check during marking | 9 |
Check only if there is a query | 5 |
Never check | 8 |
Sixteen respondents said that they checked all work, despite the considerable time this involved; six checked only a small sample of student work. Responses uncovered a variety of practices related to the use of software to check for plagiarism, and whilst most respondents did use Turnitin, others rejected it for a range of reasons and these appear to link to the nature of compliance. Three academics believed that they could spot plagiarism when it occurred; one said that they ‘did not have time to check such things’ and one said: ‘I trust my students’. Respondents also cited further reasons for not checking: three said that the university administrators conducted the checks; one claimed: ‘I don't agree with all criteria for plagiarism or whether it is as significant in the early stages of coming to understand academic life’. The results also revealed that of the respondents who were not in favour of using anti-plagiarism software (n = 11), the majority were professors (n = 7). They explained their attitudes with reference to experience/ability to ascertain cheating, saying things such as ‘I can spot when they plagiarise’ or ‘I can tell whether the work is suitable’.
Such comments suggest that perhaps more experienced academics seem to view the process of checking for plagiarism (or other types of cheating) as unnecessary, given that they either believe they can identify its occurrence or that the students should be trusted to undertake such checks themselves. Such responses led us to characterise the overall data within two themes—responsibility and roles—which are discussed in more detail in the following section.
Discussion
A range of interconnected categories was created to characterise the data from the case studies and from the responses to questions 7 and 8. In what follows, we draw attention to the two most significant themes which emerged and suggest ways in which these could be understood: first, ‘responsibility’ and second, ‘the academic role’.
Responsibility
This research found that academics could hold complicated and often contrasting views on defining their role in supporting an ethical environment in assessment (Bruton & Childers, 2016). The most influential contextual variable was found to be their views on overall responsibility. Whilst many were happy to accord the main responsibility to other parties in the ecology (students or the university), others characterised it as a shared venture.
Three respondents reminded us that the tutor generally has control over the process of assessment. Where misunderstandings arise, some of the academics believed it was because they had somehow failed in the task of assessment design. Despite one academic saying they believed that they had a ‘good moral compass’, many still wanted further guidance as they recognised the subjectivity in the marking practice and could not guarantee impartiality (Taras & Davies, 2017). Participants agreed that they could initiate the institutional procedures that support assessment, thus positioning themselves as ‘holders of ethical standards’ in a particular ‘received’ academic culture. However, three were wary of overdependence on institutional structures alone for the sustenance of an overall ethical environment. One said: ‘I feel strongly that “frameworks”, “dialogue” and “training” etc. are merely attempts to bureaucratise something that is simply not amenable to bureaucratic interference. It's probably only a matter of time before staff and students alike are required to demonstrate “ethical skills”’. Such a view is in line with Small's (2001) concerns that questions of ethics are not dealt with easily within compliance procedures.
Such compliance procedures, underpinned by university policies, usually rely on tutors upholding such regulations, but some of our respondents were failing in this regard. For example, one commented on the use of anti-plagiarism software, claiming that ‘the institution requires it but I don't do any checking myself. The students can check their own work now’. Such a response seems symptomatic of the now outdated view that this responsibility should rest entirely with students. Yet four respondents viewed the responsibility for ethical behaviour in assessment as resting mostly with the students. Whilst there may have been some disagreement over who should ultimately hold responsibility as these ‘holders of ethical standards’, some respondents felt that they needed further clarity regarding their role as an assessor. One explained: ‘… institutional structures [are needed] to support assessment in ways that promote ethical behaviours’. Such reflections seem to underline the need for a review of practice that acknowledges the complexity of these concerns because as Howard (2007) argues, this is not simply a technical matter, it requires a degree of ethical consideration on the part of the academic.
We found it curious that just five respondents saw the upholding of the ethical environment as a shared responsibility. Undoubtedly, the changing terrain of higher education in the UK makes this ideal increasingly hard to achieve. Some of our respondents stated that they felt ill-equipped to deal with troubling situations due to a lack of support from their institutions, a factor also identified by other research (see Bruton & Childers, 2016). Nevertheless, developing a shared conception of an ethical environment would require an institution-wide ‘buy-in’. As one of our respondents explained: ‘… it's about the wider flourishing and growth of the academic community and all of its members’. Despite such views which might link the ecology of individual HEIs to a broader ethical environment, sceptics might suggest that too close an alignment of the university with the overall values of society merely causes staff and students to enter into ‘Faustian bargains’ (Bruton & Childers, 2016, p.326), where ethics are influenced by accountability-driven educational aims.
Some respondents were reluctant to embrace the codification of particular ethical instances within universities. The strong sense of individualism and personal integrity still underpinning academic freedom in UK HEIs led to contrasting perspectives on responsibility. One respondent argued that we should not presume that ethics ‘… fits into a self-contained box separate from other aspects of teaching and learning’, in line with findings by Small (2001). Two other respondents felt personally accountable for the ethical implications of their work. One stated: ‘It is important that staff model exemplary ethical behaviour in all aspects of their work and explicitly stress the importance of these issues and attributes’. The overall picture that emerged suggests academics would welcome further clarity around the ethical issues involved in their professional responsibility and how to put this into practice.
The academic role
The second variable of interest is characterised by the ways in which academics perceive their particular roles as part of the overall ecology. There is some overlap between the way in which our respondents saw responsibility for the ethical environment and their view of their professional role as an academic. Nevertheless, the study highlighted elements associated with values that may have been underplayed if viewed solely as responsibility.
One subgroup of survey respondents comprised those who recognised that their personal and professional attributes were intertwined: in other words, the qualities of an ethical lecturer were more or less identical with those of an ethical person, much in line with the findings of Robie and Kidwell (2003). One respondent commented that: ‘an ethical environment is not just about academia, but life generally’. This respondent seemed to acknowledge the overlap between the personal and the institutional as being something far more expansive than regulations and codes could encompass. Another respondent described it as ‘… an environment that I was used to throughout my academic life as well as the life I am living now’. Fourteen respondents believed that personally they needed to demonstrate a commitment to shared values, common goals and openness; the same features needed to support the overall ethical environment of the university. They saw their role as encouraging the development of the same personal attributes in their students, for example ‘treating each other with respect, honesty, fairness and transparency’. But others took a less sanguine view, arguing that being ethical as a person was different from academically inappropriate behaviour and that it was the role of the academic to ensure assessment tasks ruled out opportunities for such behaviour. One respondent went so far as to claim that the student in Case Study 1—who used feedback without contributing—was actually being ‘quite smart’, but not necessarily unethical.
Our findings tentatively suggest that there was a further subgroup of respondents who viewed their role as firmly aligned with the regulations of their institution (compliance) and consequently appear to believe that any resultant blame for misconduct must then rest with their students (Peterson et al., 2011; McQueen, 2014). Some respondents accepted that academics had a responsibility for managing problems within their student cohorts as part of their professional role. However, unless their institution compelled them to act, they felt no personal responsibility to do so.
Despite their apparent differences in approach, the two subgroups identified above appeared to agree on elements of their role and how it is enacted (suggesting that compliance needs education to be fully realised). For example, institutions tend to have very carefully defined procedures in this area; nevertheless, several respondents from both groups said that students need to understand the normative concerns relating to their studies if we wish them to choose to act ethically (education). This supports research by McCabe and Trevino (1993) (amongst others) on student behaviours, suggesting that the understanding of honour codes and policies can be a key factor in their success.
Despite some respondents saying that they needed more time with students to discuss such ethical issues, there was a disconnect between their claims and their actions. Consistent with the findings of Everett (2007), the respondents agreed that such discussions with students should be happening, but few academics were actually doing so. They claimed that institutional difficulties hampered the respondents’ best intentions, with lack of time (n = 21), lack of training (n = 18), lack of clear assessment frameworks (n = 24) or a need for improved dialogue with students (n = 25) all being cited. However, the majority were seeking support for developing ways in which such issues could be embedded in their practice.
Conclusion
Carr (2001) reminds us that education is essentially a moral practice and ethical deliberation lies at its heart. All educators contribute in some way towards the support and well-being of a healthy ethical environment, not simply within their educational setting, but usually in a broader context beyond the doors of the school, college or university. The value-laden character of our roles as teachers can and should inform our pedagogy, including our attitudes and responses to assessment. With this in mind, we make three final points.
First, our suggestion of an overall framework of ecology (comprising the institution, the academics and the students) that exists within the ethical environment of the university brings together what are often viewed as disparate and sensitive issues. As previously suggested by Raisner (1997), this kind of model enables us to go beyond good/bad behaviour to consider the practical problems within this debate, and to identify the practical problems that need further exploration. We argue that being ‘ethically aware’ is a critical factor in the development of academic competence for all parties as part of the solution. How this might be achieved may look different in practice, with different HEIs prioritising a variety of pedagogical practices.
Second, institutionalising ethics through an over-reliance on codes alone could truncate our ability to think and act in new situations, therefore we need a greater understanding of the relationship between compliance and education. This quintessentially theoretical work could then lay the foundation for how HEIs might combine both aspects and enable us to adapt more effectively to new and challenging situations.
Third, this particular study on the views of academics in HEIs in the UK advances the literature in this area in three ways:
- It identifies two significant themes—responsibility and the academic role—neither of which are mentioned in any of the attendant literature covering the ethical environment or its ecologies.
- It suggests that many academics still lack clarity over how to understand the values implicit in their professional role responsibilities.
- It suggests a need, on the part of universities and academics, to invoke and support willingness to ‘try something new’ that might go beyond current practices to fulfil the ethical assessment practice in HEIs.
In the quest for improved ways in which to conceptualise and frame important values that lie at the heart of what it is to be an HEI in a continuously shifting educational landscape, the research reported here suggests some ways forward. We hope to secure funding to extend the scope of the study with larger numbers of participants, so as to be able to make some stronger claims. Small-scale studies such as this may initially appear limited in their scope, yet they serve to identify key areas of academic practice in need of further exploration.